The canonical ensemble is not the only ensemble encountered in statistical mechanics. Commonly encountered ensembles include two (slightly different) microcanonical ensembles, the grand canonical ensemble, the isothermal-isobaric ensemble, and the representative ensemble. Of some importance is the isodynamic-polythermal ensemble, which allows a rational interpretation of error in temperature measurements.
In the microcanonical ensembles, instead of fixing T the
total energy E of the system is constrained. The microcanonical ensemble includes all phase
states having given N, V, and total energy . The statistical weight
for the microcanonical ensemble is
Eq. 3.4 is often referred to as the Law of Equal a priori
Probabilities. It applies to the microcanonical ensemble, not the canonical
ensemble, a point scrambled by some authors. In the Nineteenth Century
interpretation, only phase points having exactly some energy were
treated as belonging to a given microcanonical ensemble. Tolman [7]
refers to this ensemble as a surface ensemble. In the Twentieth Century
interpretation, the laws of quantum mechanics lead to two sorts of
complication for surface ensembles:
First, if a system obeys quantum mechanics the uncertainty relation on becomes relevant. If one only measures the energy of a
system once, one can take forever to go about doing so. If the measurement
period
,
is possible, so one can
in principle say that a system has exactly energy
. A few
applications require repeated determinations of the energy of the same element
of the ensemble, in which case the
route is
unavailable.
Second, in many quantum systems the allowed values of the total energy
do not form a continuum. Instead, the allowed energies are quantized: limited
to a series of values
,
, ..., as seen in Bohr model for the
hydrogen atom. If the total energy
does not exactly match one of
the allowed energies, the ensemble contains no allowed states. Otherwise, the
ensemble contains as many states as there are degeneracies of the energy levels
having energy
. In a many-particle system, calculating exactly which
sets of molecular quantum numbers
give an
energy totalling to
can be a difficult problem in combinatorics. An
apparent simplification occurs if a single component
of the total energy has a
continuum of values. Namely, if all components of the energy other than
are quantized, and if the
total energy can be written as a sum of components, the system's total energy
is a continuum. However, for a given
,
has somewhat odd
properties. If one of the quantized energies changes,
must change so as
to keep the total energy fixed. If the total energy
is fixed,
is effectively quantized, since its value must complement the sum of the
discretely quantized energies, so as to give the correct total energy.
Complications are avoided by using a quantum microcanical ensemble in
which E is constrained to the interval . For a
macroscopic system, the skin depth
may be made incredibly small by
comparison with
, so that all states of the quantum microcanonical
ensemble have very nearly the same energy. If
is large by
comparison with the separations between the system's quantized energy levels,
the above difficulties with the surface ensemble vanish.
Either microcanonical ensemble (surface or quantum) may be envisioned as a
section of a corresponding canonical ensemble. For a system with N and V
fixed, the canonical ensemble includes all states of the system with any energy
E, . A microcanonical ensemble includes only those
states of given N and V that have prescribed energy
. If the canonical
ensemble is envisioned as a volume, a microcanonical
ensemble may be envisioned as a sheet (a surface for the surface ensemble,
or an exceedingly thin volume for the quantum microcanonical ensemble) cut out
from the canonical ensemble. Equivalently, the canonical ensemble may be
envisioned as being constructed from microcanonical ensembles the way an onion
is constructed from concentric shells of onionskin, each layer of onion
corresponding to those states of the canonical ensemble which have a particular
value of the energy. From eq. 3.1, in a constant-energy (
isodynamic) subspace of the canonical ensemble,
is a constant, exactly
as required by eq. 3.4.
If one adopts certain conventions, one can create a system very much like a canonical ensemble out of a microcanonical ensemble. Essentially, one views the canonical ensemble as being a small part (small N, small V) of a much larger (large N, large V) microcanonical ensemble. Details are found in Lecture ; suffice now to say that if a large system of fixed energy follows eq. 3.4 then a small region of it comes close to following eq. 3.1.
Some authors prefer to view the microcanonical ensemble as being the more
fundamental, the canonical ensemble being derived from the microcanonical.
These Lectures follow an alternative approach, taking the canonical ensemble
as being the most fundamental. Gibbs discusses at great length (at least for
him!) why our approach is to be preferred; the largest advantage is that
results based on the canonical ensemble remain valid for systems of few
particles, while results based on the microcanonical ensemble show anomalies as
.
A major argument in favor of eq. 3.4 as the core equation is that it is ``more fundamental'' than eq. 3.1, where by ``fundamental'' most authors mean ``simple''. The importance of simplicity, and the relative merits of largely equivalent equations, are matters of theology. Whether one begins with the canonical or the microcanonical ensemble, one needs the same number of assumptions and special entities to obtain thermodynamic behavior, so the usual form of Occam's razor will not separate them.
Some sources claim that eq. 3.4 can be derived from theoretical
considerations. The usual argument is that the Law of Equal a priori
Probabilities must be correct, because there is no reason for any state to
be preferred to any other. To this argument, an adequate response is the
child's simple ``Why? Why is there no reason?''. After all, every state of the
system has some variable(s) whose value(s) distinguishes it from every other
state. Furthermore, could have a non-trivial functional dependence on
those variables that differ from state to state, in which case some states
could be preferred to some other states.
Furthermore, the italicized argument for the Law of Equal a priori
Probabilities has no feature which causes the argument to refer specifically to
the microcanonical ensemble. If the argument ``there is no reason ...''
were correct without qualification for the microcanonical ensemble, it would
also be correct for the canonical ensemble. However,
of the canonical
ensemble is not a constant, so the argument must be wrong for the canonical
ensemble. Since the argument is wrong for the canonical ensemble, and has no
feature which depends on which ensemble one is using, the argument must also be
wrong for the microcanonical ensemble. [The argument's conclusion -- that
is a constant in the microcanonical ensemble -- is still correct, but
the argument does not prove the conclusion.] [Some sources are easy to misread
as claiming that the Assumption of Equal a Priori Probabilities is equally true
for the canonical and microcanonical ensembles. This claim is mathematically
impossible. For the canonical ensemble,
is a function of
, not a constant.]
The grand canonical, isobaric-isothermal, and isodynamic-polythermal ensembles
differ from the canonical ensemble in the variables that are held fixed, and in
the statistical weights assigned to different states. In the grand canonical
ensemble, N is allowed to vary, V, T, and the chemical potential
being held constant. In the isothermal-isobaric ensemble, N, T, and the
pressure P are fixed, V not being held rigid. The isodynamic-polythermal
ensemble holds N, V, and E fixed, but differs from the microcanonical
ensemble in its statistical weights and list of elements.
Each of these other ensembles may be constructed from a series of canonical
ensembles having different N, V, and T. The grand canonical ensemble
represents the union of all canonical ensembles having fixed V and T, but
any value of N, the relative statistical weights of
ensemble elements of different N depending on
. The isothermal-isobaric
ensemble represents the union of all canonical ensembles having fixed N and
T, but any value
of V, the relative statistical
weights of ensemble elements of different V depending on P. The
isodynamic-polythermal ensemble represents states of fixed E drawn from all
ensembles having fixed N and V,but any value
of T,
ensemble elements having the same particle positions and momenta but different
T being given equal statistical weight.
The representative ensemble appears in Gibbs as a tool for imagining, though
only imperfectly, the canonical ensemble. Gibbs' idea was that for many
purposes the canonical ensemble could be treated as consisting of a very large
but finite number N of replicas of a given system, all replicas having
the same N and V. Corresponding to each replica would be a point in phase
space. If the replicas were appropriately scattered throughout phase space, as
N became very large the representative ensemble would become more and
more like the canonical ensemble, except that the representative ensemble
contains at most a countably infinite number of points, while the number of
points in the canonical ensemble is uncountably infinite.[8] The
similarity of the two ensembles is enhanced by making the local density of
points in the representative ensemble proportional to , in
which case a simple unweighted average over all points in the representative
ensemble gives (as N
) the same result as does a
properly-weighted average over all points of the canonical ensemble.
The representative and canonical ensembles are not the same. In the
representative ensemble, the likelihood of a system occupying a specific state
of the ensemble is independent of E, the statistical weight arising from the density of points in phase space, all points in the
representative ensemble having the same statistical weight. On the other hand,
in the canonical ensemble the density of phase points is determined by the
physical nature of the system, in a way independent of temperature, the
statistical weight of a single phase point being
. We'll
discuss this difference below when we've developed some examples. It is
entirely clear from his writings that Gibbs viewed the representative ensemble
as a mental crutch. In particular, the Liouville theorem, which is a
fundamental result of equilibrium statistical mechanics, is correct for the
canonical ensemble but only an approximation for the representative ensemble.